So, the term 'common currency' is mostly used to talk about currency unions. This is, of course, where more than one political entity - usually a state - use the same currency in the sense of money.
The term used much less frequently in the sense relevant to this blog, which is with reference to decision, pattern in choices, and the processes by which choices are produced. As a result this blog is, so far, barely visible. Except for social traffic from people who pay attention to my personal activity on Facebook and Twitter, there's almost no traffic at all. Part of the problem is the dominance of what for me are irrelevant uses of 'common currency'. Even searching for "common currency brain science blog" doesn't (yet) return results where this site is anywhere near the top.
I'm going to try to take a few steps to improve matters. One of those is signing the blog up on Research Blogging, so that appropriate posts can be digested and appear in their feeds. I'll also see what I can do to generate some more inbound links.
A topic at the intersections of the philosophy of cognitive science, economics and biology.
Friday, April 26, 2013
Wednesday, April 24, 2013
Image collection: Brain dollars, dollar brains
The field of neuroeconomics has been attracting a certain
amount of popular press, and also generating a growing number of book and
special issue publications. Both of these drive appetite for illustrations. And
people sometimes seem very keen to distinguish their illustrations from the
general sorts of “pictures of brains” that go with other publications about
neuroscience. So what are they to do?
It turns out that a fairly common approach is to throw
together something that superimposes images of brains and images of cash, or
that show brains and cash in some kind of interaction.
It takes only a little thought to see that some of the
images are actually pretty silly. My reading (about common currencies) keeps taking me to places where I
see these things, and so I’m going to start collecting them and posting them
here. If you run into an image that you think belongs in the gallery, please either
comment below or email me. (I’d also really welcome pointers to good images relating to the idea of
value representation in the brain, such as the Society for Neuroeconomics logo below. This gallery is not just a Hall of Shame.)
Category 1: Brains or skulls with money on or in them
It is common to think that different motives can compete, and that that individual ones can differ in how motivating they are. At different times people have been tempted to use different metaphors to express this. When Newton was a relatively fresh and salient inspiration, it was more common to use the term ‘force’ to describe what motives had, and what some of them had more of. I’m not sure when it became popular to describe the process of deciding between competing motives as a kind of ‘weighing’, but I’d guess it was when balance scales were part of everyday experience. These days the fashionable metaphors are economic, and specifically related to cash. This is part, I think, of why ‘common currency’ talk is increasingly popular.
Exhibit 1.1: A skull with a hand holding a fan of cash in it.
Source: http://historiesofthingstocome.blogspot.com/2011/12/neuroeconomics.html |
It's not clear what to make of this. What controls a hand sticking out of the spinal column? Who or what might see or interact with the money?
Exhibit 1.2: Synapses forming a suggested dollar sign
Source: http://www.neuroeconomics.org/ |
This is the rather cool logo of the Society for Neuroeconomics. I like that the dollar sign is suggested and entangled rather than superimposed.
Exhibit 1.3: Clunky dollar signs on a murky brain
Source: http://www.apa.org/monitor/2009/01/neuroeconomics.aspx |
This one is a 'bottom of the barrel' FAIL on the APA website. It's pictures like this that made me think of posting this gallery.
Exhibit 1.4: Single clunky dollar sign on a murky brain
Source: http://xvatit.com/school/sch-online/compet/120473-urok-keys-dlya-chogo-potriben-internet-banking.html |
Exhibit 1.5: Skull looking at a dollar bill
So this is basically exhibit 1.1 above, but with the hand and the bill outside the head.
Source: http://financelongrun.blogspot.com/2013/10/neuroeconomics.html |
Category 2: Money with brains on or in it
Showing cash in or on the brain can suggest the idea of brains processing representation states related to value or utility. So some category 1 pictures can sort of make sense. The converse idea, that there might in any sense be a coherent metaphor where there are little brains in the cash, is rather farcical. This does not prevent some designers from adopting it, and some editors from approving it. Here are a few examples.
Exhibit 2.1: Dollar bills with heads and brains on them
Source: http://cas.umkc.edu/psychology/brain/current.html |
This (the logo for a project on the "Neuroeconomics of controversial food technologies") really speaks for itself. But what is it saying?
Exhibit 2.2: One Dollar bills with one brain on it
Source: http://disinfo.com/2011/11/the-neuroeconomics-revolution/#sthash.x321F4oj.dpbs |
The brain in this money is glowing. Maybe it was bitten by a radioactive banker, or something.
Category 3: Brains and money in some kind of interaction
Exhibit 3.1: The weighing metaphor, with brains and cash
Source: http://www.cns.nyu.edu/symposia/sympo2008.html |
This is pretty odd if you think about it. Unless your concern is the price of brains. Which I suppose it might be, if you were an economically active zombie. But if the brain is in the scale, then it isn't doing the weighing, or reading off the values. So what or who is? Maybe there are little brains inside brains, and the little brains do all the processing. (The same picture also appears on the cover of the important collection "Neuroeconomics: Decision Making and the Brain" edited by Glimcher, Fehr, Camerer and Poldrack. [Publisher link.])
Category 4: Miscellaneous
Exhibit 4.1: Head chart
So here's a quite fetching little image. There's no cash in the skull, or bits of brain somehow stuck onto the cash. But there's a data line of some kind that looks price-like, and with an arrowhead suggesting a projection beyond where the data runs out. It makes much more sense to think that brains represent costs and/or returns, and projects trends, than to think that they've got little banknotes in them.
Source: http://blogs.cfainstitute.org/investor/2012/02/27/bankable-insights-eight-lessons-from-neuroeconomics-for-money-managers/ |
Monday, April 22, 2013
The (very) basic big idea
Old illustration of Buridan's Ass (famously indifferent between two food options). |
If you’re struggling for a rough sense of
what the hell I’m talking about on this site, then this post is supposed to
help. It’s deliberately non-technical and informal. My aim is to give a fairly
general and intuitive sense of the idea of a common currency, and avoid the
technical details that go with how that concept is regimented in various
sciences.
Consider any two things that you want. Here
are some possibilities:
- You want each of them to about the same degree.
- You want one of them more than you want the other.
- There’s no fact of the matter about how(or whether) the degree to which you want them differs.
Now suppose that either option (1) or (2)
applies not just to the particular two things that you initially imagined, but
to every possible pair of things taken
from the whole set (possibly infinite) of things that you want.
Then your wants would form a kind of list
(possibly infinite), where every item on the list had a definite ranking
(perhaps with some on the same rankings).
Those rankings would form a kind of common
currency, like positions in a race (first, second, third, etc.). It would be common because everything you want would
be somewhere on it.
It’s important that the ranking should
include things that you don’t want
too, because (a) you should want them less
than things you positively want (possibility 1 or 2 above should apply to
each of them), and (b) because they’re not all equally horrid. This means that
we can (if we want) imagine the ranking to represent the net desirability of the things on it. (So a cupcake that costs ten
dollars, or ten minutes of effort, could come lower than the very same cupcake
for one dollar, or one minute of effort.) But we could also represent the costs
as negative wants on their own, and suppose that net desirability is calculated
(by subtracting costs from outcomes). Those are different ways of representing
the same information.
We might imagine that the strengths of our
wants are a little more quantitative. So, I might say not merely that I want a
cup of coffee more than I want a glass of water, but that I want a cup of
coffee twice as much as a glass of water. If every pair of our wants stood in
this kind of relationship, then they would all have definite relative degrees
of desirability. This would give a similarly common scale, but one that
includes information about the relative sizes of the gaps between positions.
There are at least two ways of thinking
about this ‘common currency’ scale, or dimension:
- In one case, it is a set of facts about the pattern in the actual choices you make. (One way of thinking of this is to suppose that an economist or behavioural researcher had observed a lot your activity and inferred the relative value of different outcomes from your choices. Such researchers might at least be agnostic about is be going on inside you. Many economists and behaviourists are officially agnostic about the inside, even though they’re committed to common currencies.) I’ve explained elsewhere on this blog that I find it useful to call this kind of “pattern in choices” currency ultimate.
- In the other case, it is a set of facts about the processes by which your choices are generated. One way to think about this is to think that your wants, or desires, or preferences, are real psychological states of yours. Another (which need not be the same thing) is to suppose that the strengths of your wants are represented in neural activity in your brain. I’ve explained elsewhere on this blog that I find it useful to call this kind of “process producing choices” currency proximal.
It turns out that scientists of various
kinds (including behavioural ecologists, economists, behavioural psychologists,
and neuroeconomists) argue that there is a common currency for at least some
kinds of agent. But they sometimes argue for ultimate
currencies, and sometimes proximal
ones, and they use different kinds of evidence and theory to defend their
positions.
It’s also not difficult to find examples of
people denying that there is a common
currency. Some deny it for humans, partly because they find it offensive to
suppose that our most noble wants might appear on the same scale as our most
base ones. Some deny it for some classes of animal or robot, usually saying
that internal representations (including of strength of preference) aren’t necessary
for orderly behaviour.
I’m interested in the tangle of claim and
counter-claim that this combination of arguments in favour and against produces,
when looked at comparatively. To get an idea of what I’m working on see My OwnEfforts and the links there.
See also:
Important Sources: Rodney Brooks – Denies representations for at
least some robots, so denies proximal currency.
Important Sources: Kim Sterelny – Seems to hold a position sharing
some key features with Brooks.
Important Sources: George Ainslie – Staunch defender of common
currency thesis.
Thursday, April 18, 2013
Intragenomic Conflict and Common Currencies
‘Intragenomic Conflict and Common Currencies’ is the working
title of one of the papers that is part of this common currency project. It
grew out of my reading of an essay by David Haig called ‘Intrapersonal Conflict’
which is the first piece in an anthology simply called Conflict (Cambridge, 2006, edited by M Jones and AC Fabian).
Picture showing differences between embryos of mice where genetic imprinting had been manipulated. (See the powerpoint slides below.) Image from Haig (citation below) in turn from Keverne et al. |
I presented a very preliminary version of the argument at
the 2013 conference of the PSSA, at the Salt Rock Hotel, in KwaZulu-Natal,
South Africa. Because I’d also been organizing the conference, the talk wasn’t
as worked out as it might have been.
More recently (April 17, 2013) I presented an updated
version to the senior seminar at UKZN, and I’ll be taking the same talk to the
University of Johannesburg around the end of April.
The written draft of the paper is still something of a
construction site, but my presentation slides may be of some interest, and so I’m
posting them here.
I’ll post updated slides from future presentations (right here on this page), and
eventually the working draft of the paper when it’s ready for comment and
feedback.
References
Haig D (2006)
Intrapersonal conflict. In: Jones M, Fabian AC (eds) Conflict. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 8–22.
Tuesday, April 16, 2013
Not dead, just researching
Things have been quiet here for a while, I know.
This must be a great inconvenience to my staggeringly tiny readership.
I've been working like crazy getting a working version of "Intragenomic Conflict and Common Currencies" into shape. (See My own efforts on this site. This is a paper occasioned by David Haig's "Intrapersonal Conflict". I'm also presenting a version of this at the Australasian Association of Philosophy conference in July this year.)
I'm presenting the paper tomorrow afternoon. Shortly after that, I'll probably put my slides up, so that they can bask in the blazing obscurity of this here blog. Some time after that, I may even post a working version of the paper (the prose version is still largely a construction site.) Once the presentation is done, I'll have time to finish a few draft pieces for this blog that are taking shape, and add to the preliminary discussion of important distinctions in this area.
This must be a great inconvenience to my staggeringly tiny readership.
I've been working like crazy getting a working version of "Intragenomic Conflict and Common Currencies" into shape. (See My own efforts on this site. This is a paper occasioned by David Haig's "Intrapersonal Conflict". I'm also presenting a version of this at the Australasian Association of Philosophy conference in July this year.)
I'm presenting the paper tomorrow afternoon. Shortly after that, I'll probably put my slides up, so that they can bask in the blazing obscurity of this here blog. Some time after that, I may even post a working version of the paper (the prose version is still largely a construction site.) Once the presentation is done, I'll have time to finish a few draft pieces for this blog that are taking shape, and add to the preliminary discussion of important distinctions in this area.
Tuesday, April 9, 2013
Important Sources: Rodney Brooks
Introduction
Picture of the robot 'Herbert' from: |
People who think that there is a proximal common currency[1]
for some type of agent think that the values of possible actions open to that
agent are represented in its cognitive states.
One way to deny this is to deny that agents need cognitive
states of any significant kind. This, more or less, is what Rodney Brooks went
around doing in the late 1980s and early 1990s.
Here I take a quick look at his classic 1991 paper
“Intelligence Without Representation”. I note some of the ways that it constitutes
a challenge to some views about common currencies. In his paper Brooks talks
about the design of a large class of mobile robots that he collectively calls
‘creatures’. All quotations are from Brooks (1991).
What should creatures be able to do?
In Section
(4) of his article Brooks lists some ‘requirements’ for his ‘creatures’. One of
these requirements is a reason for thinking that what he has to say is relevant to the common currency
question:
“A Creature should be able to maintain multiple goals
and, depending on the circumstances it finds itself in, change which particular
goals it is actively pursuing; thus it can both adapt to surroundings and
capitalize on fortuitous circumstances.”
This certainly gives the impression that creatures are
supposed to cope (somehow) with multiple goals and varying conditions. That’s
the sort of problem that often leads people to hypothesise a unified value
representation like a common currency.
Brooks, of course, is famously anti-representation. So
shortly after he has stated his goals, he gets down to describing the
conventional approach he rejects, which involves ‘decomposition by function’.
Here he says:
“Perhaps the strongest, traditional notion of
intelligent systems (at least implicitly among AI workers) has been of a
central system, with perceptual modules as inputs and action modules as outputs.”
While
Brooks doesn’t say so himself, this ‘central system’ is clearly the kind of
place where values (in a common currency) could be attached to possible
actions. The main reason Brooks doesn’t say so, I suggest, is that the
paradigmatic representationalist is also a cognitivist, who devotes much more
attention to epistemic states (perception, memory, reasoning) than to
motivational ones.
Next, in Section
(4.2) Brooks describes the alternative approach that he favours, which is
‘decomposition by activity’. This approach doesn’t distinguish systems by their
being central or peripheral, but rather into ‘activity producing sub-systems’ which he called ‘layers’, each of
which ‘individually connects sensing to action’:
The layers
need not all use the same sensors, or activate the same degrees of freedom. In
addition, not all processing is centralized. So, speaking of a mobile robot
built to avoid collisions, Brooks says:
“In fact, there may well be two independent channels
connecting sensing to action (one for initiating motion, and one for emergency
halts), so there is no single place where "perception" delivers a
representation of the world in the traditional sense.”
And when
layers are added, their own parochial goals can sometimes conflict over the way
to use the same degree of freedom:
‘This
new layer might directly access the sensors and run a different algorithm on
the delivered data. The first-level autonomous system continues to run in
parallel, and unaware of the existence of the second level. For example, in [3]
we reported on building a first layer of control which let the Creature avoid
objects and then adding a layer which instilled an activity of trying to visit
distant visible places. The second layer injected commands to the motor control
part of the first layer directing the robot towards the goal, but independently
the first layer would cause the robot to veer away from previously unseen
obstacles. The second layer monitored the progress of the Creature and sent
updated motor commands, thus achieving its goal without being explicitly aware
of obstacles, which had been handled by the lower level of control.”
Although Brooks makes regular references to the goals and functions of his creatures, these goals are implicit in the design
of the layers, and are not internally represented:
“The purpose of the Creature is implicit in its
higher-level purposes, goals or layers. There need be no explicit representation of goals that some central (or
distributed) process selects from to decide what is most appropriate for the
Creature to do next.” (Emphasis added.)
He’s also clear that there is competition between the
behaviours. He says that ‘each activity
producing layer connects perception to action directly’, but that while an
observer might impute central control, all that the creature is, is ‘a
collection of competing behaviors’.
So, if Brooks is correct, even if only about a limited
class of agents, then what he says poses to related challenges to the view that
orderly behaviour requires a common currency:
- He claims that there’s a way to have multiple competing goals without a proximal common currency.
- He claims that multiple competing goals can be handled without a final common control pathway.
(What I’ve said are two challenges clearly overlap a
great deal. But there are differences of emphasis at least. Also, as I’ll
explain in future postings, there is a separate ‘final common path’ argument
for a proximal currency that is independent of arguments concerning other kinds
of order in choice.)
I also note that what Brooks says doesn’t directly imply the
denial of an ultimate currency. Indeed, Brooks positively encourages the notion
that his creatures instantiate some kind of ultimate currency by frequently
saying that their behavior is ‘adaptive’. He clearly doesn’t mean that they
literally evolved under natural selection. But just as clearly he is saying
that their behavior satisfies some condition of success (perhaps even
near-optimality) at dealing with conflicting goals.
I’ll discuss some criticisms of Brooks’ position in later
postings. All I’ve really tried to do here, and for now, is note why Brooks is ‘on
the reading list’ for this project.
Related postings on this blog
Forthcoming attractions on this blog
Andy Clark on economic decisions
Proximal currencies can be cognitive or somatic
Ways of responding to Brooks’ challenge
References
Brooks, R. (1991) “Intelligence without
representation.” Artificial Intelligence 47: 139-159.
[1]
Put more carefully, this should say Cognitive
Proximal Common Currency. (Cognitive as opposed to, inter alia, somatic. This
is a distinction I’ll explain and put to work at a later date.) See Currencies can be 'ultimate' or 'proximal' and
future postings on this blog.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)